|
Whittaker
|
 |
History of Theories of Aether and Electricity
|
|
|
|
|
|
Electric and magnetic Science prior to the introduction of the potentials
|
|
THE magnetic discoveries of Peregrinus and Gilbert, and the
vortex-hypothesis by which Descartes had attempted to explain
them,[1] had raised magnetism to the rank of a separate science
by the middle of the seventeenth century. The kindred science
of electricity was at that time in a less developed state ; but it
had been considerably advanced by Gilbert, whose researches in
this direction will now be noticed.
For two thousand years the attractive power of amber had
been regarded as a virtue peculiar to that substance, or possessed
by at most one or two others. Gilbert proved [2] this view to be
mistaken, showing that the same effects are induced by friction
in quite a large class of bodies ; among which he mentioned
glass, sulphur, sealing-wax, and various precious stones.
A force which was manifested by so many different kinds of
matter seemed to need a name of its own; and accordingly
Gilbert gave to it the name electric, which it has ever since
retained.
Between the magnetic and electric forces Gilbert remarked
many distinctions. The lodestone requires no stimulus of friction
such as is needed to stir glass and sulphur into activity.
The lodestone attracts only magnetizable substances, whereas
electrified bodies attract everything. The magnetic attraction
between two bodies is not affected by interposing a sheet of
paper, or a linen cloth, or by immersing the bodies in water ;
whereas the electric attraction is readily destroyed by screens.
Lastly, the magnetic force tends to arrange bodies in definite
orientations ; while the electric force merely tends to heap them
together in shapeless clusters.
These facts appeared to Gilbert to indicate that electric
phenomena are due to something of a material nature, which
under the influence of friction is liberated from the glass or
amber in which under ordinary circumstances it is imprisoned.
In support of this view he adduced evidence from other quarters.
Being a physician, he was well acquainted with the doctrine
that the human body contains various humours or kinds of
moisture-phlegm, blood, choler, and melancholy, - which, as
they predominated, were supposed to determine the temper of
mind; and when he observed that electrifiable bodies were
almost all hard and transparent, and therefore (according to the
ideas of that time) formed by the consolidation of watery liquids,
he concluded that the common menstruum of these liquids must
be a particular kind of humour, to the possession of which the
electrical properties of bodies were to be referred. Friction
might be supposed to warm or otherwise excite or liberate the
humour, which would then issue from the body as an effluvium
and form an atmosphere around it. The effluvium must, he
remarked, be very attenuated, for its emission cannot be detected
by the senses.
The existence of an atmosphere of effluvia round every
electrified body might indeed have been inferred, according to
Gilbert's ideas, from the single fact of electric attraction. For
he believed that matter cannot act where it is not ; and hence
if a body acts on all surrounding objects without appearing to
touch them, something must have proceeded out of it unseen.
The whole phenomenon appeared to him to be analogous to
the attraction which is exercised by the earth on falling bodies.
For in the latter case he conceived of the atmospheric air as the
effluvium by which the earth draws all things downwards to
itself.
Gilbert's theory of electrical emanations commended itself
generally to such of the natural philosophers of the seventeenth
century as were interested in the subject ; among whom were
numbered Niccolo Cabeo (b. 1585, d. 1650), an Italian Jesuit
who was perhaps the first to observe that electrified bodies repel
as well as attract ; the English royalist exile, Sir Kenelm
Digby (b. 1603, d. 1665); and the celebrated Robert Boyle
(b. 1627, d. 1691). There were, however, some differences of
opinion as to the manner in which the effluvia acted on the small
bodies and set them in motion towards the excited electric;
Gilbert himself had supposed the emanations to have an inherent
tendency to reunion with the parent body ; Digby likened their
return to the condensation of a vapour by cooling ; and other
writers pictured the effluvia as forming vortices round the
attracted bodies in the Cartesian fashion.
There is a well-known allusion to Gilbert's hypothesis in
Newton's Opticks. [3]
" Let him also tell me, how an electrick body can by friction
emit an exhalation so rare and subtle,[4] and yet so potent, as by
its emission to cause no sensible diminution of the weight of the
electrick body, and to be expanded through a sphere, whose
diameter is above two feet, and yet to be able to agitate and
carry up leaf copper, or leaf gold, at a distance of above a foot
from the electrick body ? "
It is, perhaps, somewhat surprising that the Newtonian
doctrine of gravitation should not have proved a severe blow to
the emanation theory of electricity ; but Gilbert's doctrine was
now so firmly established as to be unshaken by the overthrow
of the analogy by which it had been originally justified. It was,
however, modified in one particular about the beginning of the
eighteenth century. In order to account for the fact that
electrics are not perceptibly wasted away by excitement, the
earlier writers had supposed all the emanations to return
ultimately to the body which had emitted them ; but the
corpuscular theory of light accustomed philosophers to the
idea of emissions so subtle as to cause no perceptible loss ; and
after the time of Newton the doctrine of the return of the electric effluvia gradually lost credit.
Newton died in 1727. Of the expositions of his philosophy
which were published in his lifetime by his followers, one at
least deserves to be noticed for the sake of the insight which
it affords into the state of opinion regarding light, heat, and
electricity in the first half of the eighteenth century. This was
the Physices elementa mathematica experimentis confirmata of
Wilhelm Jacob s'Gravesande (b. 1688, d. 1742), published at
Ley den in 1720. The Latin edition was afterwards reprinted
several times, and was, moreover, translated into French and
English : it seems to have exercised a considerable and, on the
whole, well-deserved influence on contemporary thought.
s'Gravesande supposed light to consist in the projection of
corpuscles from luminous bodies to the eye ; the motion being
very swift, as is shown by astronomical observations. Since
many bodies, e.g. the metals, become luminous when they are
heated, he inferred that every substance possesses a natural
store of corpuscles, which are expelled when it is heated to
incandescence ; conversely, corpuscles may become united to a
material body ; as happens, for instance, when the body is exposed
to the rays of a fire. Moreover, since the heat thus acquired is
readily conducted throughout the substance of the body, he
concluded that corpuscles can penetrate all substances, however
hard and dense they be.
Let us here recall the ideas then current regarding the
nature of material bodies. From the time of Boyle (1626-1691)
it had been recognized generally that substances perceptible to
the senses may be either elements or compounds or mixtures ;
the compounds being chemical individuals, distinct from mere
mixtures of elements. But the substances at that time accepted
as elements were very different from those which are now known
by the name. Air and the calces [5] of the metals figured in the
list, while almost all the chemical elements now recognized were
omitted from it ; some of them, such as oxygen and hydrogen,
because they were as yet undiscovered, and others, such as the
metals, because they were believed to be compounds.
Among the chemical elements, it became customary after
the time of Newton to include light-corpuscles. [6] That something which is confessedly imponderable should ever have been
admitted into this class may at first sight seem surprising. But
it must be remembered that questions of ponderability counted
for very little with the philosophers of the period. Three quarters of the eighteenth century had passed before Lavoisier
enunciated the fundamental doctrine that the total weight of
the substances concerned in a chemical reaction is the same
after the reaction as before it. As soon as this principle came
to be universally applied, light parted company from the true
elements in the scheme of chemistry.
We must now consider the views which were held at this
time regarding the nature of heat. These are of interest for our
present purpose, on account of the analogies which were set up
between heat and electricity.
The various conceptions which have been entertained
concerning heat fall into one or other of two classes, according as
heat is represented as a mere condition producible in bodies, or
as a distinct species of matter. The former view, which is that
universally held at the present day, was advocated by the great
philosophers of the seventeenth century. Bacon maintained it in
the Novum Organum : " Calor," he wrote, " est motus expansivus,
cohibitus, et nitens per partes minores."[7] Boyle [8] affirmed that
the " Nature of Heat " consists in " a various, vehement, and
intestine commotion of the Parts among themselves." Hooke [9]
declared that " Heat is a property of a body arising from the
motion or agitation of its parts." And Newton [10] asked : " Do not
all fixed Bodies, when heated beyond a certain Degree, emit
light and shine ; and is not this Emission performed by the
vibrating Motion of their Parts ? " and, moreover, suggested the
converse of this, namely, that when light is absorbed by a
material body, vibrations are set up which are perceived by the
senses as heat.
The doctrine that heat is a material substance was maintained in Newton's lifetime by a certain school of chemists. The
most conspicuous member of the school was Wilhelm Homberg
(b. 1652, d. 1715) of Paris, who [11] identified heat and light with the
sulphureous principle, which he supposed to be one of the primary
ingredients of all bodies, and to be present even in the interplanetary spaces. Between this view and that of Newton it
might at first seem as if nothing but sharp opposition was to be
expected. [12] But a few years later the professed exponents of the
Principia and the Opticks began to develop their system under
the evident influence of Homberg's writings. This evolution
may easily be traced in s'Gravesande, whose starting-point is
the admittedly Newtonian idea that heat bears to light a
relation similar to that which a state of turmoil bears to regular
rectilinear motion ; whence, conceiving light as a projection of
corpuscles, he infers that in a hot body the material particles
and the light-corpuscles [13] are in a state of agitation, which
becomes more violent as the body is more intensely heated.
s'Gravesande thus holds a position between the two opposite
camps. On the one hand he interprets heat as a mode of
motion ; but on the other he associates it with the presence of
a particular kind of matter, which he further identifies with the
matter of light. After this the materialistic hypothesis made
[1] Cf. pp. 7-9.
[2] De Magnete, lib. ii., cap. 2.
[3] Query 22.
[4] " Subtlety," says Johnson, " which in its original import means exility of
particles, is taken in its metaphorical meaning for nicety of distinction."
[5] i.e. oxides
[6] Newton himself (Oplicks, p. 349) suspected that light-corpuscles and
ponderable matter might be transmuted into each other : much later, Boscovich
(Theoria, pp. 215, 217) regarded the matter of light as a principle or element in
the constitution of natural bodies.
[7] Nov. Org., Lib. n., Aphor. xx.
[8] Mechanical Production of Heat and Cold.
[9] Micrographia, p. 37.
[10] Opticks.
[11] Mem. del'Acad., 1705, p. 88.
[12] Though it reminds us of a curious conjecture ofNewtoa'i: "Is not the
strength and vigour of the action between light and sulphureous bodies one reason
M-liy sulphureous bodies take fire more readily and burn more vehemently than
other bodies do? "
[13] I have thought it best to translate s'Gravesande's ignis by " light-corpuscles."
This is, I think, fully justified by such of his statements as Quando ignis per
lineas rectas oculos nostros intrat, ex motu quem fibris in fundo oculi communicat
ideam luminis excitat.
|
|
|