|
Whittaker
|
 |
History of theories of Aether and Electricity
|
|
|
|
|
|
The Theory of Aether in the seventeenth Century
|
|
of velocity parallel to the cloth must be unaffected by the
impact; and therefore the projection BE of the refracted ray
must be k times as long as the projection BC of the incident
ray. So if i and r denote the angles of incidence and refraction,
we have
\sin{r} = \frac{BE}{BI} = K; \frac{BC}{BA} = K\sin{i}
or the sines of the angles of incidence and refraction are in a
constant ratio ; this is the law of refraction.
Desiring to include all known phenomena in his system,
Descartes devoted some attention to a class of effects which
were at that time little thought of, but which were destined to
play a great part in the subsequent development of Physics.
The ancients were acquainted with the curious properties
possessed by two minerals, amber and magnetic
iron ore. The former, when rubbed,
attracts light bodies : the latter has the power of attracting
iron.
The use of the magnet for the purpose of indicating direction at sea does not seem to have been derived from classical
antiquity ; but it was certainly known in the time of the
Crusades. Indeed, magnetism was one of the few sciences
which progressed during the Middle Ages ; for in the thirteenth
century Petrus Peregrinus,[1] a native of Maricourt in Picardy,
made a discovery of fundamental importance.
Taking a natural magnet or lodestone, which had been
rounded into a globular form, he laid it on a needle, and marked
the line along which the needle set itself. Then laying the
needle on other parts of the stone, he obtained more lines in
the same way. When the entire surface of the stone had been
covered with such lines, their general disposition became evident;
they formed circles, which girdled the stone in exactly the same
way as meridians of longitude girdle the earth ; and there were
two points at opposite ends of the stone through which all the
circles passed, just as all the meridians pass through the Arctic
and Antarctic poles of the earth.[2] Struck by the analogy,
Peregrinus proposed to call these two points the poles of the
magnet : and he observed that the way in which magnets set
themselves and attract each other depends solely on the position
of their poles, as if these were the seat of the magnetic power.
Such was the origin of those theories of poles and polarization
which in later ages have played so great a part in Natural
Philosophy.
The observations of Peregrinus were greatly extended not
long before the time of Descartes by William Gilberd or Gilbert[3]
(6. 1540, d. 1603). Gilbert was born at Colchester: after
studying at Cambridge, he took up medical practice in London,
and had the honour of being appointed physician to Queen
Elizabeth. In 1600 he published a work[4] on Magnetism and
Electricity, with which the modern history of both subjects
begins.
Of Gilbert's electrical researches we shall speak later : in
magnetism he made the capital discovery of the reason why
magnets set in definite orientations with respect to the earth ;
which is, that the earth is itself a great magnet, having one of
its poles in high northern and the other in high southern
latitudes. Thus the property of the compass was seen to be
included in the general principle, that the north-seeking pole of
every magnet attracts the south-seeking pole of every other
magnet, and repels its north-seeking pole.
Descartes attempted[5] to account for magnetic phenomena
by his theory of vortices. A vortex of fluid matter was
postulated round each magnet, the matter of the vortex entering
by one pole and leaving by the other : this matter was supposed
to act on iron and steel by virtue of a special resistance to its
motion afforded by the molecules of those substances.
Crude though the Cartesian system was in this and many
other features, there is no doubt that by presenting definite
conceptions of molecular activity, and applying them to so wide
a range of phenomena, it stimulated the spirit of inquiry, and
prepared the way for the more accurate theories that came after.
In its own day it met with great acceptance: the confusion which
had resulted from the destruction of the old order was now, as
it seemed, ended by a reconstruction of knowledge in a system
at once credible and complete. Nor did its influence quickly
wane ; for even at Cambridge it was studied long after Newton
had published his theory of gravitation ;[6] and in the middle of
the eighteenth century Euler and two of the Bernoullis based
the explanation of magnetism on the hypothesis of vertices.[7]
Descartes' theory of light rapidly displaced the conceptions
which had held sway in the Middle Ages. The validity
of his explanation of refraction was, however, called in
question by his fellow-countryman Pierre de Ferinat (b. 1601,
d. 1665)[8], and a controversy ensued, which was kept up
by the Cartesians long after the death of their master. Fermat
eventually introduced a new fundamental law, from which he
proposed to deduce the paths of rays of light. This was the
celebrated Principle of Least Time, enunciated [9] in the form,
" Nature always acts by the shortest course." From it the law
of reflexion can readily be derived, since the path described by
light between a point on the incident ray and a point on the
reflected ray is the shortest possible consistent with the con
dition of meeting the reflecting surfaces.[10] In order to obtain the
law of refraction, Fermat assumed that " the resistance of the
media is different", and applied his "method of maxima and
minima " to find the path which would be described in the least
time from a point of one medium to a point of the other. In
1661 he arrived at the solution.[11] "The result of my work", he
writes, " has been the most extraordinary, the most unforeseen,
and the happiest, that ever was ; for, after having performed all
the equations, multiplications, antitheses, and other operations
of my method, and having finally finished the problem, I have
found that my principle gives exactly and precisely the same
proportion for the refractions which Monsieur Descartes has
established." His surprise was all the greater, as he had
supposed light to move more slowly in dense than in rare media,
whereas Descartes had (as will be evident from the demonstration
given above) been obliged to make the contrary supposition.
Although Fermat's result was correct, and, indeed, of high
permanent interest, the principles from which it was derived
were metaphysical rather than physical in character, and con
sequently were of little use for the purpose of framing a
mechanical explanation of light. Descartes' theory therefore
held the field until the publication in 1667 [12] of the Micrographia
of Robert Hooke (b. 1635, d. 1703), one of the founders of the
Royal Society, and at one time its Secretary.
Hooke, who was both an observer and a theorist, made two
experimental discoveries which concern our present subject ; but
in both of these, as it appeared, he had been anticipated. The
first [13] was the observation of the iridescent colours which are
seen when light falls on a thin layer of air between two glass
plates or lenses, or on a thin film of any transparent substance.
These are generally known as the " colours of thin plates," or
" Newton's rings " ; they had been previously observed by Boyle. [14]
Hooke's second experimental discovery,[15] made after the date of
the Micrographia, was that light in air is not propagated exactly
in straight lines, but that there is some illumination within the
geometrical shadow of an opaque body. This observation had
been published in 1665 in a posthumous work [16] of Francesco
Maria Grimaldi (b. 1618, d. 1663), who had given to the phenomenon the name diffraction.
Hooke's theoretical investigations on light were of great
importance, representing as they do the transition from the
Cartesian system to the fully developed theory of undulations.
He begins by attacking Descartes' proposition, that light is a
tendency to motion rather than an actual motion. " There is",
he observes, [17] " no luminous Body but has the parts of it in
motion more or less " ; and this motion is " exceeding quick."
Moreover, since some bodies (e.g. the diamond when rubbed or
heated in the dark) shine for a considerable time without being
wasted away, it follows that whatever is in motion is not permanently lost to the body, and therefore that the motion must
be of a to-and-fro or vibratory character. The amplitude of the
vibrations must be exceedingly small, since some luminous bodies
(e.g. the diamond again) are very hard, and so cannot yield or
bend to any sensible extent.
Concluding, then, that the condition associated with the
emission of light by a luminous body is a rapid vibratory motion
of very small amplitude, Hooke next inquires how light travels
through space. " The next thing we are to consider", he says,
" is the way or manner of the trajection of this motion through
the interpos'd pellucid body to the eye : And here it will be
easily granted
" First, that it must be a body susceptible and impartible of
this motion that will deserve the name of a Transparent ; and
next, that the parts of such a body must be homogeneous, or of
the same kind.
" Thirdly, that the constitution and motion of the parts must
be such that the appulse of the luminous body may be communicated or propagated through it to the greatest imaginable
distance in the least imaginable time, though I see no reason to
affirm that it must be in an instant.
" Fourthly, that the motion is propagated every way through
an Homogeneous medium by direct or straight lines extended every
way like Rays from the centre of a Sphere.
" Fifthly, in an Homogeneous medium this motion is propagated every way with equal velocity, whence necessarily every
pulse or vibration of the luminous body will generate a Sphere,
which will continually increase, and grow bigger, just after the
same manner (though indefinitely swifter) as the waves or rings
on the surface of the water do swell into bigger and bigger
circles about a point of it, where by the sinking of a Stone the
motion was begun, whence it necessarily follows, that all the
parts of these Spheres undulated through an Homogeneous medium
cut the Rays at right angles."
Here we have a fairly definite mechanical conception. It
resembles that of Descartes in postulating a medium as the
vehicle of light ; but according to the Cartesian hypothesis the
disturbance is a statical pressure in this medium, while in
Hooke's theory it is a rapid vibratory motion of small amplitude.
In the above extract Hooke introduces, moreover, the idea of
the wave-surface, or locus at any instant of a disturbance gene-
rated originally at a point, and affirms that it is a sphere,
whose centre is the point in question, and whose radii are
the rays of light issuing from the point.
Hooke's next effort was to produce a mechanical theory of
refraction, to replace that given by Descartes. " Because", he
says, "all transparent mediums are not Homogeneous to one
another, therefore we will next examine how this pulse or motion
will be propagated through differingly transparent mediums.
And here, according to the most acute and excellent Philosopher
Des Cartes, I suppose the sine of the angle of inclination in the
first medium to be to the sine of refraction in the second, as the
density of the first to the density of the second. By density, I
mean not the density in respect of gravity (with which the
refractions or transparency of mediums hold no proportion), but
in respect only to the trajection of the Rays of light, in which
respect they only differ in this, that the one propagates the
pulse more easily and weakly, the other more slowly, but
more strongly. But as for the pulses themselves, they will
by the refraction acquire another property, which we shall now
endeavour to explicate.
"We will suppose, therefore, in the first Figure, ACFD to be
a physical Ray, or ABC and DEF to be two mathematical Rays trajected from a very remote point of a luminous body through
an Homogeneous transparent medium LL, and DA, EB, FC, to be
small portions of the orbicular impulses which must therefore
cut the Rays at right angles : these Rays meeting with the plain
surface NO of a medium that yields an easier transitus to the
propagation of light, and falling obliquely on it, they will in the
medium MM be refracted towards the perpendicular of the
surface. And because this medium is more easily trajected than
the former by a third, therefore the point C of the orbicular
pulse FC will be moved to H four spaces in the same time that
F, the other end of it, is moved to three spaces, therefore the
whole refracted pulse to H shall be oblique to the refracted Rays
GHK and GI"
Although this is not in all respects successful, it represents
a decided advance on the treatment of the same problem by
Descartes, which rested on a mere analogy. Hooke tries to
determine what happens to the wave-front when it meets
the interface between two media ; and for this end he introduces the correct principle that the side of the wave-front
which first meets the interface will go forward in the second
medium with the velocity proper to that medium, while the
other side of the wave-front which is still in the first medium
is still moving with the old velocity : so that the wave-front
will be deflected in the transition from one medium to the
other.
This deflection of the wave-front was supposed by Hooke to
be the origin of the prismatic colours. He regarded natural or
white light as the simplest type of disturbance, being constituted by a simple and uniform pulse at right angles to the
direction of propagation, and inferred that colour is generated
by the distortion to which this disturbance is subjected in the
process of refraction. "The Ray",[18] he says, " is dispersed, split, and
opened by its Refraction at the Superficies of a second medium,
and from a line is opened into a diverging Superficies, and
so obliquated, whereby the appearances of Colours are produced."
"Colour" he says in another place, [19] " is nothing but the
disturbance of light by the communication of the pulse to other
transparent mediums, that is by the refraction thereof." His
precise hypothesis regarding the different colours was[20] "that
Blue is an impression on the Retina of an oblique and confus'd
pulse of light, whose weakest part precedes, and whose
strongest follows. And, that red is an impression on the Retina
of an oblique and confus'd pulse of light, whose strongest part
precedes, and whose weakest follows."
Hooke's theory of colour was completely overthrown, within
a few years of its publication, by one of the earliest discoveries
of Isaac Newton (b. 1642, d. 1727). Newton, who was elected
a Fellow of Trinity College, Cambridge, in 1667, had in the
beginning of 1666 obtained a triangular prism, " to try
therewith the celebrated Phaenomena of Colours." For this
purpose, " having darkened my chamber, and made a small hole
in my window-shuts, to let in a convenient quantity of the
Sun's light, I placed my Prisme at his entrance, that it might
be thereby refracted to the opposite wall. It was at first a
very pleasing divertisement, to view the vivid and intense
colours produced thereby ; but after a while applying myself to
consider them more circumspectly, I became surprised to see
them in an oblong form, which, according to the received laws
of Refraction, I expected should have been circular" The
length of the coloured spectrum was in fact about five times as
great as its breadth.
This puzzling fact he set himself to study ; and after more
experiments the true explanation was discovered - namely,
that ordinary white light is really a mixture of rays of every
variety of colour, and that the elongation of the spectrum is
due to the differences in the refractive power of the glass for
these different rays.
" Amidst these thoughts," he tells us, [21] " I was forced from
[1] His Epistola was written in 1269
[2] "Procul dubio oranes lineae hujusmodi in duo puncta concurrent sicut omnes
orbes meridian! in duo concurrunt polos mundi oppositos."
[3] The form in the Colchester records is Gilberd.
[4] Gulielmi Gilberti de Magnete, Magneticisque corporibus, et de magno magnete
tellure : London, 1600. An English translation by P. F. Mottelay was published
in 1893.
[5] Principia, Part iv, 133 sqq.
[6] Winston has recorded that, having returned to Cambridge after his
ordination in 1693, he resumed his studies there, " particularly the Mathematicks,
and the Cartesian Philosophy : which was alone in Vogue with us at that Time.
But it was not long before I, with immense Pains, but no Assistance, set myself
with the utmost Zeal to the study of Sir Isaac Newton's Wonderful Discoveries."
Whiston's Memoirs (1749), i, p. 36.
[7] Their memoirs shared a prize of the French Academy in 1743, and were
printed in 1752 in the Recueil des pieces qui ount remporte les prix de l'Acad., tome v.
[8] Renati Descartes Epistolae, Pars tertia ; Amstelodami, 1683. The Fermat
correspondence is comprised in letters XXIX to XLVI.
[9] Epist. XLII, written at Toulouse in August, 1657, to Monsieur de la
Chambre ; reprinted in (AEuvres de Fermat (ed. 1891), ii, p. 354.
[10] That reflected light follows the shortest path was no new result, for it had
been affirmed (and attributed to Hero of Alexandria) in the "book"
of Heliodorus of Larissa, a work of which several editions were published in the
seventeenth century.
[11] Epist. XLIII, written at Toulouse on Jan. 1, 1662 ; reprinted in (Euvres de
Fermat, ii, p. 457 ; i, pp. 170, 173.
[12] The imprimatur of Viscount Brouncker, P.R.S., is dated Nov. 23, 1664.
[13] Micrographia, p. 47
[14] Boyle's Works (ed. 1772), i, p. 742.
[15] Hooke's Posthumous Works, p. 186.
[16] Physico- Mathesis de lumine, coloribus, et iride. Bologna, 1665 ; book i, prop. i.
[17] Micrographia, p. 55.
[18] Hooke, Posthumous Works, p. 82.
[19] To the Royal Society, February 15, 1671-2.
[20] Micrographia, p. 64.
[21] Phil. Trans., No. 80, February 19, 1671-2.
|
|
|